
In July 1940, the first Tacoma Narrows Bridge, an engineering marvel, was completed. One of the longest suspension bridges in the world at the time, it exemplified the light, graceful architectural trend of suspension bridges built in this era. Called the crowning achievement of his career, designer Leon Moisseiff — who served as architect on the Golden Gate and Bay bridges in San Francisco — later declared, “Our plans seemed 100% perfect.”
Yet 4 months later, on November 7, 1940, the Narrows Bridge collapsed catastrophically in a typical Northwest windstorm.
Moisseiff had unshakable faith in the reliability of his newly completed masterpiece. He would have had no qualms trusting its dependability in any weather conditions. Yet had he stood upon his creation on November 7, 1940, his categorical faith in its structural integrity would have been fatal. The object of his faith was unreliable, and the strength of his faith irrelevant.
Faith is an idea frequently voiced but little understood. In today’s secular society, the term is used in a pejorative sense, where it has become a proxy for belief in the unbelievable, the unprovable, the superstitious, and the mythical. Faith has become the diametric of reason — unreasonably so, as we shall see — practiced only by deluded fools who reject scientific rationalism’s graceful catenary and steel-plate certainty.
Faith has become the diametric of reason … practiced only by deluded fools who reject the graceful catenary and steel-plate certainty of scientific rationalism.
Yet faith — not love — makes the world go round. You exercise faith when you place the key in the ignition and start your car. You have faith when you flip a switch, expecting light to rush forth from a fixture or music from stereo speakers. You have faith that your coat will keep you warm and dry, your plane will stay aloft, and your surgeon will bring you through a heart bypass. The atheist has utter faith in his reason; that belief in God is non-logical and must, therefore, be rejected. Faith therefore is nothing more than trust: a confidence that the object is reliable, the tool is trustworthy, its behavior predictable, its nature dependable. In the physical realm, such trust may be based partly on knowledge — one can study the flow of electrons and principles of resistance that make a light bulb glow — but such understanding is optional and rarely grasped by those who rely on its behavior. The object of faith may be entirely reliable yet utterly beyond our comprehension — or, as Leon Moisseiff discovered to his great dismay, deeply understood yet profoundly unreliable.
In the immaterial and spiritual realm, faith undergoes its most severe scrutiny, and is the subject of much skepticism. Such disbelief is most pronounced in the materialist, the agnostic, or the atheist — however, each of us has a potent strain of suspicion about that which cannot be weighed, measured, seen, or felt. We want to understand before we trust — and labor under the pretension that we cannot trust until we understand: until such trust is “reasonable” to the input of our senses or the perceptions and insights of the mind.
We want to understand before we trust — and labor under the pretension that we cannot trust until we understand …
Yet the countless small acts of faith that allow us to move through life are far less frequently grounded in knowledge than experience. We do not think twice about starting our cars because we have, countless times, turned the key in the ignition and seen the engine roar to life. We cross the suspension bridge without hesitation because millions have done so before us — or more proximately, because the cars in front of us are passing safely. Such experience may be personally acquired or derivative: we trust the surgeon to remove our gallbladder, not because we have directly evaluated his skills and performance, but because others have trusted before us: his reputation about their satisfactory outcome has been imputed to us. Since others have trusted before us, and their trust has been rewarded, we also find ourselves disposed to have confidence, to believe.
It is common for the skeptic to argue that spiritual or religious faith is “believing things for which there is no evidence.” However, contained within this erroneous definition is the very seed of its fallacy: it demands that the spiritual and immaterial realm be subject to the measurements, rules, and limitations of the physical. It presumes the non-existence of anything beyond that which is empirically determined. The skeptic and the materialist live in a logical lock box: their world is small indeed, allowing for naught but that which the eye may see, the hand may touch, and the mind may comprehend through its finite measure and the incompleteness of its intellectual grasp.
G.K. Chesterton, in his typically lucid and insightful way, described this straight-jacketed state of mind in his book Orthodoxy:
… [T]he materialist philosophy (whether true or not) is certainly much more limiting than any religion. In one sense, of course, all intelligent ideas are narrow. They cannot be broader than themselves. A Christian is only restricted in the same sense that an atheist is restricted. He cannot think Christianity false and continue to be a Christian; and the atheist cannot think atheism false and continue to be an atheist.
But as it happens, there is a very special sense in which materialism has more restrictions than spiritualism … The Christian is quite free to believe that there is a considerable amount of settled order and inevitable development in the universe. But the materialist is not allowed to admit into his spotless machine the slightest speck of spiritualism or miracle … The Christian admits that the universe is manifold and even miscellaneous, just as a sane man knows that he is complex. The sane man knows that he has a touch of the beast, a touch of the devil, a touch of the saint, a touch of the citizen. Nay, the really sane man knows that he has a touch of the madman.
But the materialist’s world is quite simple and solid, just as the madman is quite sure he is sane. The materialist is sure that history has been simply and solely a chain of causation, just as the interesting person before mentioned is quite sure that he is simply and solely a chicken.
Materialists and madmen never have doubts.
Reason set adrift from the divine logos floats like an airtight bottle on a sea of confusion. It fashions tightly woven arguments from false premises and constricted knowledge. It rejects the unprovable while proving the irrational. Reason may even conclude that its very foundation does not exist: that truth is a cultural artifact, that there are no absolutes. Such is the basis of postmodernism, which currently infects the lofty heights of academia, an insidious virus now replicating rapidly in the intellectual ghettos of public education and the irrational irrelevancy of college classrooms.
Furthermore, reason detached from the transcendent — the same reason upon which the materialist and the skeptic rest their insubstantial security — must be subjected to skepticism. For in the purposeless, deterministic world of random chance and unordered events, who is to say that reasoned thought and scientific inquiry is anything but the random neural energy of an accidental life form, no more connected to cause and effect than the spark that shuffled amino acids like cards into something we now call “life”?
Again, Chesterton states the problem succinctly:
[The] peril is that the human intellect is free to destroy itself. Just as one generation could prevent the very existence of the next generation, by all entering a monastery or jumping into the sea, so one set of thinkers can in some degree prevent further thinking by teaching the next generation that there is no validity in any human thought. It is idle to talk always of the alternative of reason and faith.
Reason is itself a matter of faith. It is an act of faith to assert that our thoughts have any relation to reality at all. If you are merely a skeptic, you must sooner or later ask yourself the question, “Why should anything go right; even observation and deduction? Why should not good logic be as misleading as bad logic? They are both movements in the brain of a bewildered ape?” The young skeptic says, “I have a right to think for myself.” But the old skeptic, the complete skeptic, says, “I have no right to think for myself. I have no right to think at all.”
Faith embodies the confidence in matters which we do not understand but have found to be experientially reliable. One can, almost surprisingly, have a profoundly misguided or erroneous understanding of a trustworthy object — and still, that object will remain dependable. Cro-Magnon man, magically transported by time machine to the twenty-first century, might well believe that switching on a lamp is black magic or the work of the gods — but when he flips the switch, the bulb will still emit light. Thus, faith depends, not merely on the confidence that its object will be reliable, but on the inherent reliability of the object itself.
Thus, the poles of faith are opposite yet complimentary: there must be trust, even without understanding, and the object of trust must be dependable. This paradox is at the heart of religious faith: the trust in something unseen and poorly understood, which nevertheless proves experientially trustworthy because its object is utterly reliable. Reason and faith coalesce here: reason, guided and given purpose and boundaries in the transcendent, points to what exists but is beyond our capacity to comprehend with intellect alone. Faith, on the other hand, beckons us to span this intellectual chasm with the bridge of trust, drawing us to experience that which we lack the means to grasp. Reason may block us from faith, constricted as it often is by self-imposed constraints — or reason may confirm and reinforce that which we experience by faith. Trust in the transcendent transforms us, expanding the limits and restrictions we arbitrarily place upon reality.
The man of faith sees an effect and attributes its cause to the transcendent while being open to the possibility that the cause may be random or material. The skeptic has no such freedom: the cause cannot be supernatural, for the transcendent does not exist. His viewpoint is “reality-based” only insofar as the reality he trusts excludes the supernatural. The man of faith can afford to be wrong and may often be so; such is the growth process in the unseen world. The skeptic cannot be mistaken—for his worldview is utterly demolished if he is.
However, we must confront another aspect of faith if this trust is to bear fruit in deepening our experience and understanding of the supernatural. This element is the transaction of faith: trust must be grounded in and bounded by the nature of what is trusted. A bulb will not illuminate by flipping a switch without electricity; a car will not start by placing your house key in the ignition or your music CD in the player. The nature of the object demands that the action based on trust be within fixed parameters dictated by the object’s design or character.
Much more can be considered about this transaction of faith. There is the challenge of God’s intervention (or lack thereof) in response to prayer. We seek to integrate reason, experience, and revelation into a working dynamic that broadens and deepens our horizons. We must pursue this journey far beyond the restrictive limits of the material and the mind constrained by its own finite vision. Subsequent essays will explore these and related topics — so stay tuned and go deeper into faith.
Next: Healing Faith